The following two statements appear in Bernard Williams, in “Internal and External Reasons” (in Moral Luck, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981, 101–13),
(iv) internal reason statements can be discovered in deliberative reasoning.
and
the deliberative process can add new actions for which there are internal reasons, just as it can also add new internal reasons for given actions.
There is an important difference between what these two
statements are claiming. The first says that, through deliberative reasoning,
we can discover internal reasons for an action or relationships between an
action and internal reasons. The second says that, through deliberative
reasoning, we can create new internal reasons or new relationships.
It is one thing to say that, through deliberative
reasoning, we can discover internal reasons. It is quite another to say that,
through deliberative reasoning, we can create new internal reasons.
Perhaps I am being uncharitable. Perhaps we should
simply interpret the second passage cited above as follows and go on about our
business:
the deliberative process can add to our awareness of new actions for which there are internal reasons, just as it can also add to our awareness of new internal reasons for given actions.
We would then have a statement that is consistent with
this passage:
Reflection may lead the agent to see that some belief is false, and hence to realize that he has in fact no reason to do something he thought he had reason to do.
However, Williams then says:
In his unaided deliberative reason, or encouraged by the persuasions of others, he may come to have some more concrete sense of what would be involved, and lose his desire for it, just as, positively, the imagination can create new possibilities and new desires.
Again, Williams is talking about deliberative reasoning
or the persuasions of others not only cause an agent to realize relationships
between actions and reasons for action that she was previously unaware of. He
is saying that deliberative reasoning and the persuasion of others have the
capacity to literally create and destroy desires.
There is a sense in which this is true.
We begin with a
distinction between what an agent desires for its own sake (as an end), and
what the agent desires as a means to something else.
"Desires-as-means" are bundles of desires-as-ends and beliefs.
Because deliberative reasoning and the persuasions of others have the power to
influence beliefs, they have the power to alter bundles of desires-as-ends and
beliefs. That is to say, they have the power to create or destroy
desires-as-means.
However, the reasons for action - that which actually holds the
reason to pursue the means - comes from the desires-as-ends. Desires-as-ends
are outside of the scope of deliberative reasoning and the persuasions of
others.
I think we can clear some of this up by introducing two
distinctions that seem to be being ignored here.
The first is the distinction between revealing a reason
for action (revealing a relationship between an internal reason and an action)
versus creating a reason.
The second is the classic distinction between
desires-as-ends and desires-as-means.
Deliberative reasoning can reveal relationships between
desires-as-ends and action. Thus, it can create and destroy desires-as-means.
However, it cannot create or destroy desires-as-ends. It can only reveal the
relationships between the desires-as-ends and possible actions that already
exist.
Excellent blog. We're looking for Atheist writers for our news show. We should talk. Please contact me. atheismtv at gmail
ReplyDelete